Skip to content

Commit

Permalink
Small edits
Browse files Browse the repository at this point in the history
  • Loading branch information
vprusso committed Mar 19, 2017
1 parent 4086dd5 commit d68b221
Show file tree
Hide file tree
Showing 5 changed files with 21 additions and 24 deletions.
29 changes: 13 additions & 16 deletions thesis/infinite_entanglement.tex
Expand Up @@ -87,9 +87,9 @@ \section{Quantum-classical games} \label{sec:quantum-classical-games}

In this section, we will state and prove an analogous theorem to Theorem~\ref{thm:regev-vidick-qcg} for an extended nonlocal game. That is, we will show that there exists an extended nonlocal game where the standard quantum value approaches $1$ when the dimension of the quantum systems shared by Alice and Bob approach infinity.
\begin{theorem} \label{thm:enlg-from-qcg}
Given a quantum-classical game, $G_{qc}$ with question registers $\reg{X}$ and $\reg{Y}$, there exists an extended nonlocal game, labelled as $H_t$, such that
\begin{align}
\omega^*(H_t) = 1 - \frac{ 1 - \omega^*(G_{qc}) }{\abs{\reg{X}}^2 \abs{\reg{Y}}^2}.
Given a quantum-classical game, $G_{qc}$ with question registers $\reg{X}$ and $\reg{Y}$, there exists an extended nonlocal game, labelled as $H_t$, such that
\begin{align} \label{eq:enlg-from-qcg}
\omega_N^*(G_{qc}) \leq 1 - \abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}} \left( 1- \omega^*_{N \abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}}}(H_t) \right) \quad \textnormal{and} \quad \omega_N^*(H_t) \leq 1 - \frac{ 1 - \omega^*_{N \abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}}}(G_{qc}) }{\abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}}}.
\end{align}
\end{theorem}
The main idea for proving Theorem~\ref{thm:enlg-from-qcg} will involve a successive reduction from a quantum-classical game to an intermediate type of game, called a \emph{teleportation game} (that we will define formally in the next section), and finally to an extended nonlocal game. Sections~\ref{sec:teleportation-games-and-quantum-classical-games} and~\ref{sec:extended-nonlocal-games-and-teleportation-games} are dedicated to proving Theorem~\ref{thm:enlg-from-qcg}. Specifically, in Section~\ref{sec:teleportation-games-and-quantum-classical-games}, we will show how quantum-classical games are related to teleportation games, and in Section~\ref{sec:extended-nonlocal-games-and-teleportation-games}, we will show how teleportation games are related to extended nonlocal games. Once these relationships are established, we will be able to prove Theorem~\ref{thm:enlg-from-qcg}.
Expand Down Expand Up @@ -172,7 +172,7 @@ \subsection{Teleportation games and quantum-classical games} \label{sec:teleport
for all $N \geq 1$.
\end{lemma}

Prior to proceeding to the proof, we give a brief sketch to provide some intuition. In order to prove the lemma, we must prove both that $\omega_N^*(G_{qc}) \leq \omega_{N \abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}}}^*(G_t)$ and that $\omega_{N}^*(G_t) \leq \omega_{N\abs{\reg{X}}\abs{\reg{Y}}}^*(G_{qc})$.
Prior to proceeding to the proof, we give a brief sketch to provide some intuition. In order to prove Lemma~\ref{lem:qcg_eq_telep}, we must prove both that $\omega_N^*(G_{qc}) \leq \omega_{N \abs{\reg{X}} \abs{\reg{Y}}}^*(G_t)$ and that $\omega_{N}^*(G_t) \leq \omega_{N\abs{\reg{X}}\abs{\reg{Y}}}^*(G_{qc})$.

In the first inequality, we assume that Alice and Bob play honestly. That is to say, we assume that Alice and Bob play along and allow the referee to teleport registers to Alice and Bob. For this to happen, the initial state is prepared as a maximally entangled state and Alice and Bob also apply the appropriate Pauli teleportation corrections on their respective systems after they receive the questions from the referee. This direction of the proof is simply illustrating how such a strategy is carried out when Alice and Bob play honestly and is depicted in Figure~\ref{fig:teleportation-game-strategy}.

Expand Down Expand Up @@ -315,24 +315,21 @@ \subsection{Extended nonlocal games and teleportation games} \label{sec:extended
\end{align}
according to the uniform distribution and sends $x \in \SigmaA$ to Alice and $y \in \SigmaB$ to Bob. Alice responds with $a \in \GammaA$ and Bob responds with $b \in \GammaB$.

\item The referee prepares a state $\rho \in \Density(\X \otimes \S \otimes \Y)$ and performs a measurement
\begin{align} \label{eq:bell-basis-telep-game-2}
\left \{ \phi_{x_1}^{(\abs{\reg{X}})} : x_1 \in \SigmaA \right \} \subset \Pos(\X \otimes \X_1) \quad \textnormal{and} \quad \left \{ \phi_{y_1}^{(\abs{\reg{Y}})} : y_1 \in \SigmaB \right \} \subset \Pos(\Y \otimes \Y_1)
\end{align}
on registers $(\reg{X},\reg{X}_1)$ and $(\reg{Y},\reg{Y}_1)$ yielding outcomes $x_1$ and $y_1$. The referee then performs a measurement with respect to the binary-valued measurement $\{ P_{a,b,x,y}, \I - P_{a,b,x,y} \}$ where
\item The referee prepares a state $\rho \in \Density(\X \otimes \S \otimes \Y)$ and then performs a measurement with respect to the binary-valued measurement $\{ P_{a,b,x,y}, \I - P_{a,b,x,y} \}$ where
\begin{equation} \label{eq:ref-meas-telep-enlg}
\begin{aligned}
P_{a,b,x,y} &= \I - \phi^{(\abs{\reg{X}})}_{x} \otimes \left( \I - Q_{a,b} \right) \otimes \phi^{(\abs{\reg{Y}})}_y, \\
\I - P_{a,b,x,y} &= \phi^{(\abs{\reg{X}})}_{x} \otimes \left( \I - Q_{a,b} \right) \otimes \phi^{(\abs{\reg{Y}})}_y, \\
\end{aligned}
\end{equation}
where $\{Q_{a,b}, \I - Q_{a,b} \} \subset \Pos(\S)$. The outcome corresponding to the measurement $P_{a,b,x,y}$ indicates that Alice and Bob win, while the other measurement indicates that they lose. Implicit in the winning and losing measurements is the relationship between $(x,y)$ and $(x_1,y_1)$ that
where $\{Q_{a,b}, \I - Q_{a,b} \} \subset \Pos(\S)$. The outcome corresponding to the measurement $P_{a,b,x,y}$ indicates that Alice and Bob win, while the other measurement indicates that they lose.
\end{enumerate}
As further intuition for the above protocol, we shall see that the last step may be thought of as a form of \index{post-selected teleportation}{\emph{post-selcted teleportation}} where the randomly selected questions $x$ and $y$ are compared to $x_1$ and $y_1$ which are hypothetical measurement results that would be obtained if the referee were to perform teleportation. Implicit in the winning and losing measurements is the relationship between $(x,y)$ and $(x_1,y_1)$ that
\begin{enumerate}
\item \emph{If $x \not= x_1$ or $y \not= y_1$}: The referee immediately accepts, and therefore Alice and Bob win.
\item \emph{If $x = x_1$ and $y = y_1$}: The referee performs a measurement with respect to the binary-valued measurement $\{Q_{a,b}, \I - Q_{a,b} \}$ on register $\reg{S}$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{enumerate}
As further intuition for the above protocol, we shall see that the last step may be thought of as a form of \index{post-selected teleportation}{\emph{post-selcted teleportation}} where the randomly selected questions $x$ and $y$ are compared to $x_1$ and $y_1$ which are hypothetical measurement results that would be obtained if the referee were to perform teleportation. That is, in the event where $x \not= x_1$ or $y \not= y_1$, this corresponds to a failure to teleport $\reg{X}$ or $\reg{Y}$ to Alice or Bob. Likewise, the event where $x = x_1$ and $y = y_1$ corresponds to the event where teleportation protocol would have succeeded, since if the referee \emph{were} to teleport, it would have sent $x_1$ and $y_1$ to Alice and Bob, which would influence the measurement that they would apply to their system. Since in this case $x = x_1$ and $y = y_1$ it is \emph{as if} the referee were to teleport $\reg{X}$ to Alice and $\reg{Y}$ to Bob.
That is, in the event where $x \not= x_1$ or $y \not= y_1$, this corresponds to a failure to teleport $\reg{X}$ or $\reg{Y}$ to Alice or Bob. Likewise, the event where $x = x_1$ and $y = y_1$ corresponds to the event where teleportation protocol would have succeeded, since if the referee \emph{were} to teleport, it would have sent $x_1$ and $y_1$ to Alice and Bob, which would influence the measurement that they would apply to their system. Since in this case $x = x_1$ and $y = y_1$ it is \emph{as if} the referee were to teleport $\reg{X}$ to Alice and $\reg{Y}$ to Bob.

\begin{proof}[Proof of Lemma~\ref{lem:telep-to-enlg}]
Let $H_t$ be the extended nonlocal game as introduced above, and let it be defined in terms of the same state and measurement operators
Expand Down Expand Up @@ -472,10 +469,10 @@ \subsubsection*{Proof of Theorem~\ref{thm:enlg-from-qcg}}
\begin{align}
1 - \frac{1 - \omega_{N}^*(G_t)}{\abs{\reg{X}}^2\abs{\reg{Y}}^2} = \omega_N^*(H_t).
\end{align}
It then follows that
\begin{align}
\omega^*(H_t) = 1 - \frac{1-\omega^*(G_{qc})}{\abs{\reg{X}}^2\abs{\reg{Y}}^2}.
\end{align}
It then follows that the inequalities from equation~\eqref{eq:enlg-from-qcg} hold.
%\begin{align}
% \omega^*(H_t) = 1 - \frac{1-\omega^*(G_{qc})}{\abs{\reg{X}}^2\abs{\reg{Y}}^2}.
% \end{align}
Furthermore, it follows from Theorem~\ref{thm:regev-vidick-qcg} that there exists a quantum-classical game $G_{qc}$ where $\omega_N^*(G_{qc}) = 1$ is achieved in the limit as $N$ goes to infinity. It then follows that there also exists an extended nonlocal game $H_t$, where $\omega_N^*(H_t) = 1$ as $N$ approaches infinity.
\end{proof}

Expand Down
2 changes: 1 addition & 1 deletion thesis/monogamy-games.tex
Expand Up @@ -267,7 +267,7 @@ \section{Parallel repetition of monogamy-of-entanglement games} \label{sec:paral
\begin{align}
\omega(G)^r \leq \omega(G^r) \leq \omega(G).
\end{align}
It may be tempting to conclude that $\omega(G^r) = \omega(G)^r$ for all games, however this was surprisingly disproven~\cite{Fortnow1990, Feige1991, Verbitsky1996, Feige2002}. Specifically in~\cite{Fortnow1990}, Fortnow introduced a game $G$ for which $\omega(G^2) > \omega(G)^2$. This result was later improved by Feige~\cite{Feige1991}, by exhibiting an example of a game where $\omega(G^2) = \omega(G)^2$ with $\omega(G) < 1$.
It may be tempting to conclude that $\omega(G^r) = \omega(G)^r$ for all games, however this was surprisingly disproven~\cite{Fortnow1990, Feige1991, Verbitsky1996, Feige2002}. Specifically in~\cite{Fortnow1990}, Fortnow introduced a game $G$ for which $\omega(G^2) > \omega(G)^2$. This result was later improved by Feige~\cite{Feige1991}, by exhibiting an example of a game where $\omega(G^2) = \omega(G)$ with $\omega(G) < 1$.

We say that a game $G$ exhibits the property of \index{strong parallel repetition}{\emph{strong parallel repetition}} if the value of the game raised to the $r$ power is equal to the value of running the game $r$ times. For instance, a monogamy-of-entanglement game, $G$, where the players use a standard quantum strategy satisfies strong parallel repetition if and only if
\begin{align}
Expand Down
12 changes: 6 additions & 6 deletions thesis/preliminaries.tex
Expand Up @@ -135,7 +135,7 @@ \subsubsection*{Operators}

\subsubsection*{Norms}

For any complex Euclidean spaces $\X$ and $\Y$ and any operator $A \in \Lin(\X,\Y)$, we define the \index{norm}{\emph{norm}} of $A$, denoted as $\norm{A}$, as a function which satisfies the following conditions:
For any complex Euclidean spaces $\X$ and $\Y$ and any operator $A \in \Lin(\X,\Y)$, we define a \index{norm}{\emph{norm}} of $A$, denoted as $\norm{A}$, as a function which satisfies the following conditions:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\norm{A} \geq 0$ for all $A \in \Lin(\X,\Y)$,
\item $\norm{A} = 0$ if and only if $A = 0$ for all $A \in \Lin(\X,\Y)$,
Expand Down Expand Up @@ -306,7 +306,7 @@ \subsection{Convexity and semidefinite programming}

\subsubsection*{Convexity}

We shall denote finite-dimensional real or complex vector spaces as either $\V$ or $\W$. In this section, the space $\V$ will typical denote either $\real^n$ or $\complex^n$, for some finite $n > 1$, and $\W$ shall be a subset of $\V$. We say that a set $\W \subseteq \V$ is \index{convex}{\emph{convex}} if for all $u,v \in \W$ and all $\lambda \in [0,1]$ it is true that
We shall denote finite-dimensional real or complex vector spaces as either $\V$ or $\W$. In this section, the space $\V$ will typically denote either $\real^n$ or $\complex^n$, for some finite $n > 1$, and $\W$ shall be a subset of $\V$. We say that a set $\W \subseteq \V$ is \index{convex}{\emph{convex}} if for all $u,v \in \W$ and all $\lambda \in [0,1]$ it is true that
\begin{align}
\lambda u + (1-\lambda)v \in \W.
\end{align}
Expand Down Expand Up @@ -373,17 +373,17 @@ \subsubsection*{Hilbert spaces}
\begin{align}
\sum_{n \in \natural} \bigip{ \abs{A} e_n}{e_n} < \infty,
\end{align}
where $\abs{A}$ denotes that $A^*A$ is positive and therefore has a square root $\sqrt{A^*A} \in \B(\H)$. For $A \in \B(\H)$, define
where $\abs{A} = \sqrt{A^*A} \in \B(\H)$. For $A \in \B(\H)$, define
\begin{align}
\norm{A}_1 = \sum_{n \in \natural} \bigip{\abs{A}e_n}{e_n}.
\end{align}
We may therefore say that a bounded operator $A \in \B(\H)$ is also trace class if $\norm{A}_1 < \infty$. A density operator $\rho \in \B(\H)$ is both a bounded operator and a trace class operator.

Let $\H$ be a Hilbert space and let $s(n) = u_n$ with $u_n \in \H$ for all $n \in \natural$ be a sequence in the space $\H$. Then we say that the sequence $s$ \index{weak-* convergence}{\emph{converges weak-*}} to a vector $u \in \H$ if
Let $\Y$ be a Banach space and let $\X = \Y^*$. Then we say that a sequence \index{weak-* convergence}{\emph{converges weak-*}} to a vector $f \in \X$ if
\begin{align}
\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \ip{u_n}{v} = \ip{u}{v},
\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} f_n(v) = f(v),
\end{align}
for all $v \in \H$. A consequence of the so-called \index{Banach-Alaoglu theorem}{\emph{Banach-Alaoglu theorem}}~\cite{Rudin1991} that we will use in Chapter~\ref{chap:extended_npa_hierarchy} is that every bounded sequence has a weak-* convergent subsequence.
for all $v \in \Y$. A consequence of the so-called \index{Banach-Alaoglu theorem}{\emph{Banach-Alaoglu theorem}}~\cite{Rudin1991} that we will use in Chapter~\ref{chap:extended_npa_hierarchy} is that every bounded sequence has a weak-* convergent subsequence provided $\Y$ is separable.

%We first define the notion of convergence for infinite-dimensional spaces. Let
%\begin{align}
Expand Down
Binary file modified thesis/thesis.pdf
Binary file not shown.
2 changes: 1 addition & 1 deletion thesis/thesis.tex
Expand Up @@ -254,7 +254,7 @@ \chapter*{APPENDICES}
% Add the References to the Table of Contents
\addcontentsline{toc}{chapter}{\textbf{References}}

\bibliography{refs_jab}
\bibliography{../refs_jab}
% Tip 5: You can create multiple .bib files to organize your references.
% Just list them all in the \bibliogaphy command, separated by commas (no spaces).

Expand Down

0 comments on commit d68b221

Please sign in to comment.